I have recently been informed that I am “outside of the sociology” of academic philosophy. (The person who said this of me is someone I like and admire, and whose presence on the scene I value, very much.) I think this means, for one thing, that I do not display a number of the shibboleths that are commonly used by members of the clan to identify other members, like Vikings with their brooches. Sometimes this is because I refuse to display them, and sometimes this is because I am unaware that they exist.
One of the most common shibboleths, of which I have been aware since grad school, is that one must ostentatiously grumble about all those times when strangers, for example seat neighbors on airplanes, innocently ask “what [your] philosophy is”. One is supposed to complain to fellow clan members that hoi polloi do not even know that a true philosopher does not “have a philosophy”, all while delicately avoiding use of a term like “hoi polloi” that might make explicit the class-based nature of this disdain.
Here’s the thing though: I do have a philosophy, and I like being asked what it is. So this is two strikes against me in my already contested petition for residence within the sociology of philosophy (a residence I had too casually assumed permanent when I got my Ph.D. and went out into the world and just kept doing philosophy). But when I explain what my philosophy is, rather than simply acknowledging that I have one, that's when I really risk being taken for an outsider. Here we are not talking about a mere shibboleth or vocational tic, but about which of the historical legacies of philosophy we wish to see carried over into the future.
I recognize that I am on the losing side, that the historical legacies that I value, and that have in some places and times constituted the paradigm for doing philosophy, seem so strange today that I sound as if I must simply not know what philosophy is when I try to defend them. But that is not my problem. My work is to keep forgotten alternatives alive in the hope and expectation that they will one day again be valued.
Part of this work, conceived in this way, is ‘merely’ doxographical, and there are legitimate reasons why we do not think that Diogenes Laërtius or Isidore of Seville are great philosophers, or why we think that people setting themselves up as latter-day Isidores might not be deserving of the highest perks and accolades the discipline has to offer. Yet the line between dead doxography and living traduction of tradition is not so clear, and I would like to think that doing critical editions and translation of past figures is a form of real contribution to philosophy. This form is more valued in Europe than in America, where there is greater awareness of the difficulty of escaping tradition (about this more below) and in at least this one respect I acknowledge that I have been Europeanized.
I am currently in the United States for my longest sojourn here since 2002, and after so many years away it seems to me that my distance from the culture of American academic philosophy is to some extent only a single dimension of my distance from American culture as a whole. My encounter with American philosophy so far, since arriving in late August, might be summed up as follows:
[Scene: a post-conference reception, somewhere in America]
Young American philosopher: “I work on forgiveness, and Louis C. K. trying to make a comeback so soon? That’s not OK.”
American philosophy establishment: Great stuff, great stuff.
Me: I’m, uh, finishing up a critical edition of Pierre Gassendi’s 1657 Syntagma Philosophicum.
American philosophy establishment: How curious. You must be very erudite, but not really part of the sociology of philosophy.
Where, I wonder, is the Henry James of today, who could make sense of this dialogue des sourds, the great novel of manners that would again lay bare the American character through the mirror of the Old World?
In any case what I wanted to do here was to try to show why attachment to currently undervalued or perhaps totally forgotten conceptions of the philosophical project —attachment of the sort that leads a person to spend years of a life plugging away at translating and editing obscure Latin works— might constitute a positive contribution to philosophy, and might be worthy of a place in the contemporary sociology of the discipline.
Some of my guiding lights in philosophy are Aristotle, Petrus Ramus, G. W. Leibniz, Walt Whitman, and Cornel West. Together they help to give shape to a set of enduring commitments, a philosophy, that I have come to think of as “ecstatic rationalism”. I think I can summarize it under four principal headings, all of which overlap with and inform the others in fundamental ways.
1. Knowledge of universal truths comes through particulars, and adequate attention to any particular can be as useful for coming to know general truths as any attempt to contemplate these truths directly in circumventing the particulars. Thus, to draw an example from Aristotle, a tide pool filled with marine invertebrates is as good a setting as any for doing philosophy, as the structure and diversity of the perishable individual forms found there provides a key into the nature of the divine and eternal (or whatever updated but still basically equivalent terms you prefer). Thus what is sometimes called Aristotle's “invitation to biology”:
If we can go along with Whitman this far, and imagine that we know dinosaurs and minerals and so on because their being is a part of the being of our own souls, then a fortiori we will find the contemporary demand to “stay in your lane”, epistemologically speaking, offensive and strange.
Obviously, standpoint epistemology is usefully invoked in certain pragmatic contexts, as a check on our tendency to casually assume we know what another's experience is like without really thinking about it. But the transformation of this pragmatic principle, mostly a matter of basic respect, into some kind of deep ontological divide between people who in fact share quite a bit, into a metaphysics of windowlessness minus the doctrine of universal mutual containment, is offensive to reason and to imagination at once. You think you do not know what it is like to be a person born into a different situation? Imagine harder. You think you do not know what it is like to be a factory-farmed calf being prodded down the gauntlet to its death? How convenient for you, but you're not imagining hard enough. Ecstatic rationalism despises the idea of “allyship”, which is the more overtly political expression of the ontology of windowlessness without mutual containment. I do not want to be your ally. I want to be your kin. Anything less is a waste of your time and mine.
4. I have been using “ecstatic” mostly in its literal sense, that of being outside of oneself. There is another more common usage of it in which it overlaps with something like “histrionic”, and I mean at least to suggest this too. Leibniz was ecstatic only in the first sense, while Whitman is ecstatic in both senses. It is the possibility of this sort of Whitmanian ecstasy that I think is the greatest legacy of American philosophy. It is embodied for example by Cornel West, who understands his own philosophical work on the model of jazz improvisation, and traces this as much to the literature of the so-called American Renaissance as he does to jazz itself. (He has also found himself in career trouble at various times as a result of his insistence on engaging with philosophy in this mode, but in his case it was both a prejudice against a certain style of thought, as well as simple racism, that created the perfect cocktail of controversy; I only have to worry about the first sort of hazard.) Here is West, speaking on the figure of Black Guinea in Melville's The Confidence-Man (1857):
“You have to understand, that grotesque Negro cripple... is part of my own heritage. Because what you actually have there is a jazz-like figure, an improvisational figure on the ropes, a figure who’s able to use smoke and mirrors not just to survive catastrophe but to try to maintain a certain kind of sanity and dignity, a certain kind of compassion, and a certain kind of hope... That’s why Black Guinea inspires me to try to be a blues man in the life of the mind, to play jazz in the world of ideas. And Melville? He’s my agnostic comrade and democratic companion!”
Whitman and West, and indeed Melville too, embody the free-wheeling engagement with learnedness that erudite Europeans can easily read as superficiality. But it is important to interpret this new American position on “book-learning” correctly. Whitman, as usual, does so with remarkable clarity:
"... current American philosophy, which [...] pursues answers to philosophical questions from within the bubble of the small sector of contemporary American culture that it takes for reality itself." Crippling indictment, wholly accurate. It's repeated in other realms of American society, including our political culture and foreign policy, not just under Trump, but generally. It's like we only see reflections of America when we look beyond our shores, a willful blindness or fata morgana. Why is this so pervasive and rarely noticed or interrogated?
Posted by: edward rackley | November 19, 2019 at 08:55 AM
Well-written, and thanks. I think you undersell rigor - it is present in your work. Perhaps moreso.
Posted by: JJWeisman | November 20, 2019 at 02:17 PM
zippy la low bogey and down, thanks !
Posted by: Grant | November 21, 2019 at 04:48 PM
Ecstatic Rationalism! A two word effervescent poem, delightful and so provocative. Merci, Professor Smith.
Posted by: David Keith Johnson | November 23, 2019 at 12:35 AM
Having myself abandoned American philosophy graduate school in 1976, I see your point. However, I think little of being erudite for its own sake and am not impressed by the writings of Walt Whitman. You have sort of backed yourself into a corner, because academic philosophy is a joke and your eloquent writing could never be popular enough to provide a significant income. Perhaps, living in Europe, you could follow an ancient European tradition and find yourself a wealthy patron, though that too has disadvantages.
Posted by: Paul | November 23, 2019 at 08:46 AM